CAPITAL - Massiness of Capital |
Limits to Harvey:I The Massiness of Capital Journal of Australian Political Economy, 70, Summer 2012-13, pp. 25-46. When I was a graduate, everyone said
they were Marxist, but hardly anyone had read any Marx … In a way, the stronger
the cultural consensus about a figure, the less likely anyone will inquire. The
great wheels of civilisation turn around terms that mean nothing, that have no
core. Marilynne Robinson, Spectator, 26 May 2012. Because
developing the tactics and strategy to promote the interests of the exploited,
even for resistance, is chancier if we lack clarity on the intricacies of our
enemy, the crisis in accumulation this time has cornered many of us into
reposing the question “what is capital?”. One path proceeds through the couplings
of constant/variable, fixed/fluid, individual/social and competitive/monopolising.
Penetrating those complexities lays a foundation for distinguishing “fictitious”
from “finance” and “financial”. (McQueen, 2009; 2011a) This paper builds on
those investigations to consider how the expansion of capital depends on the
engagement of objects/things with processes through historically specific relations.
The analysis begins from Marx’s acceptance
that a dimension of thing-hood inhabits capital, before introducing four instances
which do not meet the everyday sense of thing, namely, human capacities;
personal services; ephemeral commodities and money. The next segment approaches
capital at the intersection of value-forms and social relations. Metamorphosis
is then offered as a corrective to the sub-dialectical reasoning of casting
thing against process. Although the commentary rarely strays beyond exegesis, such
theoretical practice can rise above coquetting with concepts if our eye is on making
sense of the latest blockage in accumulation. The origins and prognosis of the
catastrophe are outside the province of this paper, though elements are
traversed elsewhere. (McQueen, 2010) Our focus on these tasks is
sharpened by an engagement with David Harvey’s lifetime of investigation into contemporary
capitalism. Across forty years, he has guided Left activists through Marx’s
critique of political economy. As part of a broader critique of his oeuvre, this essay circles his claims
that capital is not a thing but rather a process. Interrogating this dichotomy becomes
politically valuable if it cautions against either/or thinking since critiquing
the trajectories of capital calls for a method in which “contradiction is both
realised and resolved.” (Marx, 1976: 198) “down with
the object!” (Marx & Engels, 1956: 32) In
a habitual if common enough misstep,[1]
Harvey writes that “[c]apital, Marx insists, should be defined as a process
rather than as a thing” (Harvey, 1982: 20). One exception reports that “in
Marx’s definition, capital is constituted as both the process of circulation of value (a flow) and the stock of
assets (‘things’ like commodities, money, production apparatus) implicated in
those flows.” Within a dozen pages, however, this summation is displaced by the
regular claim that, for Marx, “[c]apital
is directly conceptualised, therefore, as a process
or as a relation rather than as a
‘thing’.” (Harvey, 1996: 49-50, 62-63) Harvey emphasises process and circulation
rather than the social relations of production, which is a more usual
definition of capital among Marxists, as he once put it: But capital is the social power of
money used to make more money, most typically through a form of circulation in
which money is used to buy commodities (labour power and means of production)
which, when combined within a particular labour process, produce a fresh
commodity to be sold at a profit. (Harvey, 1985: 25) To
view capital as “the social power of money … through a form of circulation” is
superior to focusing on “a process of circulation”. (Harvey, 2010c [2]) Had
Harvey struck to this version there would be less need to unstitch his account.
Strikingly though, he does not here
name surplus-value as the source of profit – an oversight connected to his
by-passing of the valorisation process in favour of the labour process as
conjoint parts of the production process. (McQueen, 2012b) Marx pursues the
substance of capital through the twofold character of that process so that, far
from saying that capital is “a process of circulation”, he shows why the latter is one phase in the reproduction
process as a whole. But in the process of circulation, no value is produced,
and thus no surplus-value. The same value simply undergoes changes of form.
Nothing at all happens except the metamorphosis of commodities, which by its
very nature has nothing to do with the creation or alteration of value. (Marx,
1981: 392) Value
cannot be generated and hence capital cannot grow inside a “process of
circulation.” Accumulation requires both a labour process and a valorisation
process. (Marx, 1976: 283-306) Stress on capital as a process,
whether of circulation or production, pales
beside Marx’s elaboration of its circuits
in volume two where he
specifies how money, production and commodities take part in each other’s
expansion. For instance, capital steps forth as money, usually credit, to buy
several things, namely, raw materials, semi-finished goods and ancillaries, but
crucially, labour-power. The first pair of those production-commodities remain
things during their remaking to emerge as material constituents in the new things
to be exchanged. Too often, Marxists never get to relax the simplifying
assumption in the formula of Money-Commodities-More Money (M>C>M+) from
volume one to penetrate volume two for its trio of circuits (e.g. M-C … P …
C+-M+) with all the massiness of exploitation and labour discipline that makes
expansion possible. (McQueen, 2011b) In elaborating those circuits, Marx sees
that capital “is a movement, a
circulatory process through different stages, which itself in turn includes
three different forms of the circulatory process. Hence it can only be grasped
as a movement, and not as a static thing.”[2]
(Marx, 1978: 185) The phrase “static thing” reminds us that it is things that
are in motion so that capital can expand. Their movement does not require their
de-materialisation. In writing that “[c]apital is not a thing but exists only
in motion” (Harvey, 2010a: 40), Harvey sidelines the things that are moving
through the production process where they shift from one use-value to another
as bearers of additional exchange-value. Before specifying further inadequacies
in any splitting of thing from process, it needs to be said that Harvey is
right to challenge the bookkeepers’ identification of capital with “a stock of
productive assets” to depreciate. (Harvey, 1996: 49) He is also right to acknowledge
process and circulation since capital cannot be a thing in the sense of being
an inert lump, whether of gold or steel, worked up as coins or girders. Notwithstanding
these truths, the defects flow from severing processes from things, the more so
if process is chained to circulation. The phrase “process of circulation” remains
empty until we know what is in circulation – money, commodities or – dare one
say it – things? Harvey extends his mantra to “fixed
capital”, which is that segment (mostly plant and machinery) of the means of
production, almost none of which circulates in commodities, Nonetheless, Harvey
writes that “[f]ixed capital is not a
thing but a process of circulation of capitals through the use of material
objects, such as machines.” (Harvey, 1982: 205) To picture fixed capital in
circulation is a category error. At least the oxymoron accepts that capital
expands through “material objects.” The bracketed insertions below bring the sentence
more into line with Marx’s treatment: Fixed capital is not [just] a [single]
thing but [one element in] a process of circulation of [money and fluid]
capitals [for their expansion] through [the application of labour and] the use
of other material objects, such as machines. This
rewrite remains inadequate since it omits the class relations that allow exploitation
and produce surplus-value. No amount of wordplay will decide the
nature of capital. To reach an answer, we must venture into its behavior. Only
by considering its reproduction can we clarify the interlocks and disjunctures
between things, processes and relations across the more than 200 years since
value became self-valorising[3]
and capital entered upon its own mode of production. Thereafter, capital could
be itself only when in the business of expanding. This essential is highlighted
whenever the circuits for growth are thrown into reverse so that values previously
materialised as means for further expansion start to shrink: Machinery which is not used is not
capital. Labour which is not exploited is equivalent to lost production. Raw
material which lies unused is no capital. Buildings (also newly built
machinery) which are either unused or remain unfinished, commodities which rot
in warehouses – all this is destruction of capital. (Marx, 1968[4]:
495; cf. 1976: 425) In
these cases, commodities “not only lose their use-value, but do not alter the magnitude of their value.” (Marx, 1956:
295) They cease to be capital. Capital is lost because the non-use of the things
in which it is embedded has depleted their use-values and thereby shrunk their
possible contribution to the next round of growth in exchange-values. Marx’s
portrayal of these negations suggests that he was not keen to strip capital of
palpable forms. Marx notes that, although J.S. Mill
recognises that capital is a “production relation”, he “confuses capital with
the material elements of which it is constituted.” (Marx, 1971: 236) In making
such criticisms, Marx never forgets “how important is the analysis of use-value for the determination of economic
phenomena” (Marx, 1968: 489) and so does not suppose that a “production
relation” can be severed from its physical forms. Rather, capital must not be
reduced to those constituents even though it usually “consists of commodities
or, in so far as it consists of money, it must be reconverted into commodities
of one kind or another, in order to be able to function as capital.” (Marx,
1968: 533) Almost all of those
commodities are also things, from bibles and brandy to rifled cannon. Elsewhere,
Marx illustrates why even a gift of nature has to be made flesh by pointing out
that wind can contribute to production only if capitalists possess things,
namely, windmills to harness that ancillary. (Marx, 1981: 784) It seems
Quixotic to suppose that capital can be comprehended by tilting at things. Capital is much more than the
use-values in which it is usually embodied since its expansion swivels on
surplus-value and exchange-values to yield any profit. Despite the distinctions
that Marx draws between value-forms, he recognises that use-values remain the
“material substratum of exchange-value, are the bearers of exchange-value.”
(Marx, 1976: 293; cf. 1981: 375) Although use-values are the “material shell”
of exchange-values, the latter “do not contain an atom of use-value” because
exchange-value “can have no more natural content than has, for example, the
rate of exchange” and, like “weight”, is a quality which no chemist or
physicist can extract. (Marx, 1976: 167n., 128, 176, 148-9) Processes alter the significance of things
without liquidating their presence since “[v]alue exists only in
use-values, in things, if we leave aside its purely symbolic representation in
tokens.” (Marx, 1976: 310) When writing about the average rate of profit as
“ossified”, Marx inspects capital simultaneously as relationship and thing: In this quite alienated form … capital
more and more acquires a material form, is transformed more and more from a
relationship into a thing, but a thing which embodies, which has absorbed, the
social relationship, a thing which has acquired a fictitious life and
independent existence in relation to itself, a natural-supernatural entity; …
(Marx, 1971: 483) In volume three, Marx reminds us of
how capital is - and is not - married to things: But capital is not a thing, it is a
definite social relation of production pertaining to a definite historical
social formation, which simply takes the form of a thing and gives this thing a
specific social character … It is the means of production monopolised by a
particular section of society … and … personified in capital through this
antithesis. (Marx, 1981: 953) The
distinction that Marx draws here counterpoises “thing” to “process” yet ties them
together within relations of production, neither dissolving their physical forms, nor disconnecting them from the
processes to which they contribute. Hard cases Human
capacities, human services, ephemera and money are expressions of capital which
are beyond our everyday useage of thing but nonetheless retain a physical
dimension. Sketches of these four cases confirm the place that Marx reserves
for objects throughout the circuits of capital. Living tools The
character of one of the things employed in processes for the expansion of value
amazes when the exchange of labour-power for wages alienates human capacities
into a form of capital: “What is in fact brought to market is not labour, but
the labourer. What he sells to the capitalist is not his labour but the
temporary use of himself as a working power.” (Marx, 1971: 113) This sale of
labour-power installs thing-ification: “(Man himself, viewed merely as the
physical existence of labour-power, is a natural object, a thing, although a
living, conscious thing, and labour is the physical manifestation [dingliche Ausserung] of that power.)” (Marx,
1976: 310) Throughout the production process, the wage-slave is the embodiment
of labour-time while the capitalist personifies capital, whom Marx dramatises
as Mr Glass Capital or Mr Moneybags. Members of neither class lose their
human-ness when they encounter the other
as things. Such duality is as typical of each value-form and every capital-form
as it is of Marx’s method. Personal services Related
to the reification of human capacities is whether personal services can expand capital.
Adam Smith rightly allots them according to whether or not they enlarge
resources for accumulation, in short: do they produce surplus value? That was
not the situation with the services supplied to Smith at home by his valet.
However, when he booked into an inn which provided him with servants, his
relationship with those flunkies moved from personal service paid for out of
his revenue to one of wage-slavery producing surplus-value for the inn-keeper.
(Marx, 1956: 154, 160-1, 168) Marx knew of other commoditiesthat are animate: Are there not at every moment of time
in the market, alongside wheat and meat, etc., also prostitutes, lawyers, sermons,
concerts, theatres, soldiers, politicians, etc.? These lads or wenches do not
get the corn and other necessaries or pleasures for nothing. In return they
give or pester us with their services, which as such services have a use-value
and because of their production costs also an exchange-value. Reckoned as
consumable articles, there is at every moment of time, alongside the consumable
articles existing in the form of goods, a quantity of consumable articles in
the form of services. (Marx, 1956: 164, cf. 392) Although
these services/commodities have next-to-no shelf-life, they are not aethereal
but are supplied and received through bodily organs expressive of their thinghood.
Ephemera The
grounds for dispelling doubts about whether personal services can contribute to
expansion need not apply to ephemeral commodities. Domestic service might be
drawn out over a lifetime whereas amusements are more often fleeting and hence
do not exist “in a more or less durable, and therefore again saleable, use-value
…” Marx, therefore, appreciates that exchange-value “depends on the degree to
which the use-value is durable, that is, on how slowly consumption deprives it
of the possibility of being a commodity
or bearer of exchange-value.” (Marx, 1956: 294) Wants that arise from our fancy
enlarge the question mark over whether exchange-value can ride on a use-value that
is barely durable. Through a contrast of extremes, Marx proposes that it could:
“Diamonds and song are both congealed labour and can – like all commodities –
be converted into money and as money into capital.” (Marx, 1968: 137; cf. 1970:
28) However, for as long as song bore the
liability of needing to be “consumed while it is being performed” (Marx, 1956:
168), an impresario could profit only from ticket sales for its recital. That
circumstance led Marx to suppose that “capitalist production is hostile to
certain branches of spiritual production, for example, art and poetry.” (Marx,
1956: 277) Nonetheless, he saw that the printing of books had already removed some
of this impediment to accumulation: A writer is a productive labourer not
in so far as he produces ideas, but in so far as he enriches the publisher who
publishes his works, or if he is a wage-labourer for a capitalist ... For example
Milton, who wrote Paradise Lost for
five pounds, was an unproductive labourer.
On the other hand, the writer who turns out stuff for his publisher in factory
style, is a productive labourer. (Marx,
1956: 153-4; 389) Marx’s
stricture against the bourgeois Philistine shed its aptness as agents of
capital found ways to commodify more of the arts, turning ineffectual angels
into productive labourers - productive, that is, of surplus value. Technologies
have allowed the incorporation of ever more performances into durable goods: screen
acting helps television networks to package audiences for sale to marketers
(Smythe, 1977); erotic services
and divine guidance are bought through phone-sex and televangelism; Pavarotti’s
singing became a vendible commodity as CDs and DVDs. (Klumpenhouwer, 2002) i-Tunes
warded off the threat from Napster to the realisation of surplus-value so that
“spiritual production” is now available at the super-market check-out. Such inventions
confirm that the expressions of capital are historical, neither eternal,
natural nor universal. The
money-commodity Marx
adjusts his handling of the interweave of process, thing and relationship to
that most multi-faceted manifestation of capital - money. The key to his
analysis is that money is itself a commodity, albeit one with unique
properties. Within capitalism, money serves as a measure of value; a medium of
circulation; a store of value; and world money. In meeting these needs, money appears
in a variety of physical guises, from precious metals to plastic tokens. Gold is
among the most durable of commodities yet, even in its alloyed form as sovereigns,
it was worn away by being exchanged.
One of Marx’s rollicking paradoxes illumines why the intimacy between gold and
money persists after gold ceases to be the monetary standard: But the gold coin gave rise first to
metallic and then to paper substitutes only because it continued to function as
a coin despite the loss of metal it incurred. It circulated not because it was
worn, but it was worn to a symbol because it continued to circulate. Only in so
far as in the process of circulation gold currency becomes a mere token of its
own value can mere tokens of value be substituted for it. (Marx, 1970: 114) These
symbols retain their link back to gold because they too stand as universal
equivalents of socially necessary labour-times, those measures of variable
capital embodied in every commodity, including precious metals. Once capital is the product of its own
reproduction, money becomes the most mysterious of the system’s operations,
epitomising fetishism yet increasingly detached from the primary object of worship
– gold. The capitalist system floats on credit, an intangible promise, one which
underwrites fictitious capital. With the sprawl of credit, money seems to be independent
of coins as well as of the commodities that it represents during an exchange of
values: The social existence that it [money] has
thus appears as something beyond, as a thing, object or commodity outside and
alongside the real elements of social wealth. Credit, being similarly a social
form of wealth, displaces money and usurps its position. It is confidence in
the social character of production that makes the money form of products appear
as something merely evanescent and ideal, as a mere notion. (Marx, 1981: 707-8) This
dream world, crowded by capital, commodities and money as phantoms, is
shattered as soon as credit is shaken … all the
real wealth is supposed to be actually and suddenly transformed into money,
into gold and silver – a crazy demand, which, however, grows necessarily out of
the system itself. (Marx, 1981: 708) The
opening phase of a crisis precipitates a rush back to that “barbarous relic”. (Cochrane,
1980-81) Of late, this “crazy demand” has been at work in the flight to gold in
China and in chatter at the World Bank about reverting to a quasi-gold standard.
Worse is in store for conjurors of credit
once gold proves not to be hard enough. Only within capitalism, does gold shed
its lustre while commodities are losing value. As the depression deepens, its
hoarders flee towards ready money, as
Marx had witnessed in 1858 during perhaps the first global crisis: This particular phase of world market
crises is known as monetary crisis. The summum
bonum, the sole form of wealth for which people clamour at such times, is
money, hard cash, and compared with it all other commodities – just because
they are use-values – appear to be useless, mere baubles and toys … mere
ornament and gluttony. (Marx, 1970: 146) Similarly,
in our era of excess capacity, the funds released by US and European central
banks are being recycled into government bonds rather than outlaid on public works.
This grand larceny cannot rescue the financial system since “[c]redit depends
on the confidence that the exploitation of wage labour … will continue in the
traditional manner.” (Marx, 1977: 170) That underpinning requires state apparatuses
to enforce class power at workplaces and beyond. Social relations Our
quest to refine the interpretation of capital, which began from a juxtaposing of
process against thing, now moves towards integrating those characteristics into
a range of relationships. All
manifestations of capital, like any account of it, remain abstract until
located in the structured dynamics of value-forms, those “social expressions” of the “world of commodities.” (Marx,
1976: 160) While capital-forms were still growing out of value-forms in the
1800s, they fertilised each other and the relations between them, each set gaining
momentum from their cross-links without surrendering all of their
distinctiveness. To uncover how value-forms operate together involves specifying
the kind of “social” in each since not all these relations are between human
beings. Although labour is common to all forms of capital and of value, each
has its specific social dimension: use-values
gain a social element if their utility is sought by someone other than their
makers or current owners; value is a
relation through the socially necessary labour-time required to achieve the
average rate of profit; exchange-value
“is a relation between persons …. hidden by a material veil” since it is
expressed between several kinds of commodities. (Marx, 1970: 34) Sorting through these value-forms is bedeviled
by the switches that Marx makes in his terminology. (Young, 1976) He confesses that
he had been “wrong” to open Capital in
the “customary manner” by calling the commodity “both a use-value and an
exchange-value”, a version he corrects[5]
by interpolating “value” between use-value and exchange-value: “A commodity is
a use-value … and a ‘value’. It appears as the twofold thing it really is as
soon as its value possesses its own particular form of manifestation … [in] exchange-value
…” (Marx, 1976: 152) This twofold nature of a commodity is founded on its
utility and exchange: Commodities come into the world in the
form of use-values, or material goods, such as iron, linen, corn, etc. This is
their plain, homely, natural form. However, they are only commodities because
they have a dual nature, because they are at the same time objects of utility
and bearers of value. Therefore they only appear as commodities, or have the
form of commodities, in so far as they possess a double form, i.e. natural form
and value form. (Marx, 1976: 138) The
social dimension of exchange-values exists while being compared with other
goods or services: “the commodity never has this form [exchange-value] when
looked at in isolation, but only when it is a value-relation or an exchange
relation with a second commodity of a different kind.” (Marx, 1976: 152) That comparison
can explode to encompass the galaxy of commodities because one of the money-forms serves as a universal equivalent for
comparing their socially-necessary labour-times: Commodities, which exist as
use-values, must first of all assume a form in which they appear to one another nominally as exchange-values, as definite
quantities of materialised universal
labour-time. The first necessary move in this process is, as we have seen, that
the commodities set apart a specific commodity, say, gold, which becomes the direct reification of universal labour-time
or the universal equivalent. (Marx, 1970: 64-5) Some
of the relations between money and labour-time have been sketched above but it
is well to remember that commodities possess an
objective character as values only in so far as they are all expressions of an
identical social substance, human labour,
that their objective character as values is therefore purely social. From this
it follows self-evidently that it can only appear in the social relation
between commodity and commodity. (Marx, 1976: 138-9) In
recognising that accumulation pivots on such comparisons, Marx need not expel
or decompose the materiality of capital as an accumulation of values but rather
must relocate its “natural form” within social labour: … the exchange-value of things is a mere expression, a specific
social form, of the productive activity
of men, something entirely different from things and their use as things … Thus
commodities, things in general, have value only because they represent human labour, not insofar as
they are things in themselves, but insofar as they are incarnations of social
labour. (Marx, 1971: 181) Thus,
a commodity is a peculiar kind of thing. A stick lying on the forest floor
becomes one only after it has been collected for barter or sale. That
incorporation of value does not destroy its stick-ness. The obverse remains
true as Marx indicates when he analyses Ricardo’s labour theory of value to
accuse one of its critics of accepting the fetishistic appearance of things as
if that aspect could exhaust their social reality and thereby boil their value
down to a physical property open to chemical experiment: Thus he, the wiseacre, transforms
value into something absolute, “a property of things”, instead of seeing in it
only something relative, the relation of things to social labour … in which
things are defined not as independent entities, but as mere expressions of
social production. (Marx, 1971: 130) That
social relations are one element in the definition of capital is a spur to refining both social and relation. Although relations are of the essence, not all
are valid. Indeed, the granting of significance to relations is risible when
economists connect “capital, land and labour”, which, as Marx observes, have as
little relation to each other as “lawyer’s fees, beetroots and music.” (Marx,
1981: 953) He sunders the trinity of “profit, rent and wages” because those sources of income are not
fungible: First, we have the use-value land, which has no value, and the
exchange value rent: here, then, a
social relation, conceived as a thing, is placed in a relationship of proportion with nature;
i.e. two incommensurable magnitudes are supposed to have a proportionate ratio.
(Marx, 1981: 956) Marx
is again able to redeem value and things from abstraction by clarifying relationships.
Are monads relational? David
Harvey’s alertness to relations entices him into the quasi-dialectical Idealism
of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716), a thinker who gets little attention from
Marxists. (McQueen, 2012c) The geographer in Harvey remains fascinated by
Leibniz’s view that space is not a thing, not one of Newton’s containers which
exist even if devoid of places, but rather is some kind of relation. Before
Harvey was any sort of Marxist, he had “identified a tripartite division in the
way space could be understood” (Harvey, 2006: 121) which he summarised in his
first Marxist work, Social Justice and
the City, by concluding that [t]here is another sense in which
space can be viewed as relative and I choose to call this relational space –
space regarded in the manner of Leibniz, as being contained in objects in the
sense that an object can be said to exist only insofar as it contains and
represents within itself relationships to other objects. (Harvey, 1973: 13) This
description of the properties of an object owes little to Leibniz for whom the
belief in space between or within objects was an insult to the plentitude of
God’s Perfection, a conviction which led him to challenge Newtonian gravitation
as action at a distance. Leibniz came to believe that the world is made up of
monads, a term he takes from “Monas … a Greek word which signifies
unity, or that which is one …. having no parts.” (Leibniz, 1934: 21) Harvey’s
reading of Leibniz transfers certain characteristics of monads as simple
substances to those composite ones. This blurring allows Harvey to suppose that
each monad “internalises everything there is” which is contrary to Leibniz’s faith
that God internalises the universe inside each of them at its creation. They
are self-contained, indivisible and impenetrable which makes it impossible for
them to internalise anything: “Monads have no windows … Thus neither substance
nor accident can enter a monad from without.” (Leibniz, 1934: 7) Harvey
substitutes an activity - “internalising” - for Leibniz’s more passive
“mirroring”, a capacity which confines the relations that a monad can have with
the outside to perceptions; its internal relations are similarly limited to
consciousness, which is inevitable given that the monad is immaterial, mind,
soul. When Harvey theoreticises space, he
invokes Descartes, Einstein and Leibniz to conjure connections with Marx’s
three forms of value: Everything that pertains to use value
lies in the province of [Cartesian] absolute space and time … Everything that
pertains to exchange value lies in [Einstein’s] relative space-time because
exchange entails movements … Value is, however, a relational concept. Its
referent is, therefore, [Leibniz’s] relational space-time. (Harvey, 2006: 141) These
associations are strained since not everything about each value-form fits with the
proffered variants of spatio-temporality: use-value is more than extension when
it is the bearer of exchange-value; the movements entailed in exchange-value
depend on a prior comparison of values, leaving value no more “relational” than
exchange-value. Harvey extends his representation of the
monad as being open to outside relations to argue that understanding “a
category like ‘money’ ” is impossible “without examining the way it internalises
all sorts of other meanings such as commodity, labor, gender, status, memory,
capital, and the state.” (Harvey, 2006: 271) Leaving aside that that this concern
is epistemological, not with an ontology of social relations, it remains the
case that if money were a Leibnizian monad, those other “meanings” would have
been supplied by God and could not be the outcome of the “massiness” of human
action over the past 250 years, as an historical materialist must maintain. Harvey
also advances an account of money which simultaneously runs counter to monads
as “unified”, “simple substances” and abandons Marx’s structured dynamics: Money … has multiple uses and it is
quite possible for each use to define a different spatio-temporality. Yet money
is, in the end, just money so the term operates as a kind of umbrella to
indicate a wide range of “compossible” or “congredient” uses of a consistent
and coherent entity endowed with certain qualities. The fact that some of these
uses may be contradictory vis-à-vis
other uses in no way detracts from the overarching coherence of the money
concept. (Harvey, 1996: 260) Flattening
money into “just money” jettisons the insights that Marx attained about how its
four functions can be performed only in each other’s company. Moreover, once
money is reduced to a uniform entity, the forms of capital and value are also leveled
to “just capital” and “just values”. From the perspective of Flatland, Harvey can
go on to argue that, because “[v]alue is, in short, a social relation … it is
impossible to measure except by way of its effects …”. (Harvey, 2006: 142) If
so, there is no role for money as the universal equivalent, the measure of value
as a manifestation of labour-time.[6] Leibniz’s
concepts of relational space-time and the monad support Harvey’s de-materialising
of capital. Although acknowledging Leibniz’s Idealism, Harvey convinces himself
that he can “drop the theological” for “a secularised version.” (Harvey, 1996:
252-4) Such hopes are not easily fulfilled as many have found with Kant or Hegel.
After cracking the monad’s deist shell, its kernel remains god-structured, with
Leibniz’s “Author of nature” as pure action matching Harvey’s capital as process.
His creation of the monad’s capacity for internalising relations allows him to
welcome Leibnitz’s treatment of space and
time as dialectical whereas Leibniz
accepts internal modifications but denies any effect from other monads, leaving
little space for dialectics, either as method or in actuality. The monad’s lack
of parts means that it is free of contradiction, qualitative changes and leaps;
for dialectical materialists, that triad works for and against each other, both
within and between all forms of value, money and capital. Dialectical reasoning In
penetrating the conundrum of capital as a clutch of relationships, processes,
value-forms and things, we have been steeping ourselves in dialectical
reasoning - albeit like Moliere’s bourgeois gentleman, M. Jourdain, who had
spoken prose all his life without announcing it. How often is the appearance of
“dialectical” in a text academic abracadabra, a sign that the topic is too
complicated for the author to unravel? Harvey’s “Introduction” to his recent Companion to Marx’s ‘Capital’ notes the
difficulty of reasoning dialectically, a burden he lightens by contracting dialectics
to motion: “Dialectics has to, in short, be able to understand and represent
process, change and transformation.” (Harvey, 2010b: 11) This stress on the dialectic
as movement confirms the one-dimensional mentality evident in the casting of thing
against process. Materialist dialecticians go beyond “process, change and
transformation” to ponder the manner in which they operate: is the movement
“cyclical” or “ spiral”? (Marx, 1976: 727, 780; 1968: 524); since most change
is quantitative, not qualitative, need motion always be dialectical, or can it be
mechanical within a dialectical totality? In addition, quantitative-to-qualitative
transformations involve rates of
change, not just its presence, as is the case for turnover-times. (Marx, 1978: 233-424) Furthermore, Marx never lauds the dynamics
within capitalism to the extent of supposing that its expansion could be free
from blockages, i.e. the crises that arise out of the spatial and temporal gaps
between production and consumption that are peculiar to the capitalist mode. On
the contrary, he brings the reciprocities between the active and the inert to
the fore in tracking the tides of money as the measure of labour-time: So that money as coin may flow
continuously, coin must continuously congeal into money. The continual movement
of coin implies its perpetual stagnation in larger or smaller amounts in reserve
funds of coin which arise everywhere within the framework of circulation and
which are at the same time a condition of circulation. (Marx, 1970: 126) Businesses
maintain latent capital as money to minimise interruptions in their production
processes. Some capital as money is always suspended, awaiting the moment to be
cast again into the circuits for accumulation. Similarly, Marx traces the
intimacies between motion and inertia into the critical component for expansion
- “labour” - as it “constantly undergoes a transformation, from the form of
unrest [Unruhe] into that of being [Sein], from the form of motion [Bewegung] into that of objectivity [Gegenstandlichkeit],” recognising “that
this inactivity is the prerequisite of its movement.” (Marx, 1976: 296; 1970:
126n.) During the production process, variable-capital is alternatively in states
of “unrest” and “being”, see-sawing from value-adding activity to a “static
thing”. Although values are added only during “unrest”, the at-rest stage is
part of the social metabolism making expansion possible. Metamorphosis Searching
for a metaphor to accommodate multiple forms and their interplays, Marx
favoured Ovid’s “metamorphosis” to picture how capital expands while
transforming one kind of thing into another.
Wonder of wonders, capital, which, in one of its aspects, can be
called value in process – and since
value only exists independently in money, it can accordingly be called money in process, as it goes through a
series of processes in which it preserves itself, departs from itself, and
returns to itself increased in volume. (Marx, 1971: 137) Throughout
this metempsychosis, capital cannot be identified with any single thing since it must be embodied in several different kinds
of things, and synchronously so if it is to be exchanged via money. Even at its
most mundane as a raw material, commodity-capital becomes two kinds of thing at
each instant during the production process where it is not what it had been on
entering but is still not the object it will be on the market after alloys are
moulded into car-parts or seeds germinate to yield a sorghum crop: … in the labour process … – materials
of labour, instruments of labour and labour – begin to ferment, act on one
another, combine with one another, undergo a chemical process and form the
commodity like a crystal as a result of this process. (Marx, 1971: 490) As
production commodities acquire new uses they reappear in different commodities with
a larger aggregation of exchange-values. For example, labourers make cement,
admixtures and sand into concrete slabs, a new use-value and the bearers of both
more exchange-value and office towers. The duality in the commodity as thing
and as social relation, and as both use- and exchange-values, is revealed in
the need that value has to be some kind of thing without caring which: “however
important it may be to value that it should have some use-value to exist in, it
is still a matter of complete indifference what particular object serves this
purpose.” (Marx, 1976: 310-11) Steel might be turned into a chair or a bridge.
The expansion of capital requires that the exchange-value of the steel in each new
commodity be realised at the average rate of profit, or better. Furniture is as
handy at that as is a freeway. This shape-changing is at its most
spectacular for the universal equivalent of commodities – money: “All
commodities can be converted into money and as money into capital, because in
the form of money their use-value and
their particular natural form become extinct.” (Marx, 1968: 137) Money can nowadays
flutter free as a key-stroke while fluctuations in exchange-rates remain tethered
to the “world of commodities.” Value transcends the attributes specific to
thingness without vaporising “natural forms” while it awaits the call to metamorphose
yet again through the three circuits of capital - ad infinitum prays every capitalist. Contra-concluding One
objection to keeping “thing” in our definition of capital will come from those
whose fondness for Capital is
confined to a couple of pages under the rubric “The Fetishism of the Commodity
and its Secret”. The fetishisation of this sub-heading allows cultural
theorists and Post-ists to squib Marx’s critique of political economy with the
“fatiguing climb of its steep paths.” (e.g. Milner, 2011: 1-2) In the 1960s, their
ilk distilled estrangement from the Economic
and Philosophical Manuscripts to soar above the massiness of alienation as
the sale of labour-power. (Walton and Gamble) Desirous of floating free from the
“world of commodities”, shame-faced materialists find “nothing more damnable,
more profane, more massy than an object”, which sullies their speculative philosophising.
(Marx & Engels, 1956: 32) By contrast, the validity of keeping things
in sight when accounting for any disruption in the accumulation of capital proves
ineluctable when its physical forms are commanded to vanish. The survival of capital
depends of its expansion which is impossible without an increase in the means
of production, without new machines, more raw materials, more semi-finished
goods, more ancillaries – more of every kind of thing save one. That exception
is living labour if and when it is displaced by dead labour, the machine-thing.
Such transmogrification is central to crisis theory because the compositions of
social capital effect the tendential law of the rate of profit to fall. Every
crisis in the capitalist mode manifests itself in an over-production of things
as the bearers of surplus value that cannot be realised as profit for further
expansion. Were capital no more than an agglomeration
of things, however, there would never have been a capitalist mode of
production. Within capitalism, there are no things without processes, no
processes without things, and neither outside relationships. Investigating all
three – and more – is required to comprehend capital as the “self-expansion of
values.” The job facing materialist dialecticians is to integrate our
understanding of every form of value and of capital in order to locate the fulcra
upon which those with naught to sell except labour-power can tip class power in
their favour. References Clarke,
Simon (1982), Marx, Marginalism and
Modern Sociology, From Adam Smith to Max Weber, Macmillan, London. Cochrane,
Peter (1980-81), “Gold: The Durability of a Barbarous Relic”, Science & Society, vol. 44, No. 4,
pp. 385-400. Harvey,
David (1969), Explanation in Geography,
Edward Arnold, London. Harvey,
David (1973), Social Justice and the City,
Edward Arnold, 1973. Harvey,
David (1982), The Limits to Capital,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Harvey,
David (1985), “Money, Time, Space and the City”, Consciousness and the Urban Experience, studies in the history and
theory of capitalist urbanisation, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore,
MD. Harvey,
David (1990), The Condition of
Post-Modernity, Blackwell, Cambridge, Mass. Harvey,
David (1996), Justice, Nature, and the
geography of difference, Blackwell, Cambridge, Mass. Harvey,
David (2006), Spaces of global capitalism, Verso, London. Harvey,
David (2010a), The Enigma of Capital: and
the Crises of Capitalism, Oxford University Press, London. Harvey,
David (2010b), Companion to Marx’s
Capital, Verso, London. Harvey,
David (2010c), davidharvey.org/2010/08/the-enigma-of-capital-and-the-crisis-this-time Klumpenhouwer,
Henry (2002), “Commodity-form, Disavowal, and Practices of Music Theory”,
Regula Burckhardt Qureshi (ed.), Music
and Marx, Ideas, Practice, Politics, Routledge, London, pp. 23-41. Leibniz,
G. W. (1934), Philosophical Writings,
J.M. Dent, London. McQueen,
Humphrey (2003), “What happened in Globalisation”, Journal of Australian Political Economy, No. 51, pp. 103-31. McQueen,
Humphrey (2009), “Re-fining capital” McQueen,
Humphrey (2010), “Chinese Crackers” McQueen,
Humphrey (2011a) “Fictitious capital” McQueen,
Humphrey (2011b), “Who’s afraid of volume two?” McQueen,
Humphrey (2012a), “Assemblage of the Initial Capital” McQueen,
Humphrey (2012b), “Harvey and valorisation” McQueen,
Humphrey (2012c), “Harvey’s ‘Leibnizian Conceit’ ” Marx,
Karl (1956), Theories of Surplus-Value I,
Foreign Languages Publishing House (FLPH), Moscow. Marx,
Karl (1958), Capital I, FLPH, Moscow. Marx, Karl (1966b), Das
Kapital, zwiete band, Europaische Verlagsandstalt, Frankfurt am Main. Marx,
Karl (1968), Theories of Surplus-Value II,
Progress Publishers, Moscow. Marx,
Karl (1970), A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy, Progress Publishers, Moscow. Marx,
Karl (1971), Theories of Surplus-Value
III, Progress Publishers, Moscow. Marx, Karl (1973), Grundrisse,
Penguin, Harmondsworth. Marx, Karl (1976), Capital
I, Penguin, London. Marx,
Karl (1977), Marx-Engels Collected Works, vol. 8, Lawrence and Wishart, London. Marx,
Karl (1978), Capital II, Penguin,
London. Marx,
Karl (1981), Capital III, Penguin,
London. Marx,
Karl and Frederick Engels (1956), The
Holy Family, FLPH, Moscow. Milner,
Andrew (2011), “Changing the Climate”, Arena
Journal, No. 35-36, pp. 1-7. Oakley,
Allen (1985), Marx’s Critique of
Political Economy, Intellectual Sources and Evolution, Volume 2, Routledge
& Kegan Paul, London. Smythe, D.W. (1977), “Communications:
Blindspot of Western Marxism”, Canadian
Journal of Political and Social Theory, vol. 1, No. 3, pp. 1-27. Young,
Gary (1976), “A Note on Marx’s Terminology”, Science & Society, vol.
40, no. 1, pp. 72-78. [1] Other example include: “Capital is a process and not
a thing” (1990: 343); “Capital is not a thing but a process” (2010a: 40);
“Capital is not a thing, but rather a process” (2010b: 12); “Capital, Marx
insists, is a process of circulation and not a thing.” (2010c: [2]; cf. 1982:
205) Harvey is in good company among Marxists in excising
“thing-hood” from capital. Simon Clarke quotes a few words from the Grundrisse to disparage those who see
“capital ‘as a thing, not as a relation’.” (Clarke 1982: 78) This italicised
snatch misrepresents the point that Marx is arguing against Adam Smith’s
ahistorical extraction of tools from social labour. In Smith’s opinion, the
human hand is capital. Marx counters: “The catch is that if all capital is
objectified labour which serves as means for new production, it is not the case
that all objectified labour which serves as means for new production is
capital.“ Only after this statement do we find the sentence from which Clarke
has drawn his assertion: “Capital is
conceived as a thing, not as a relation.”(Marx, 1973: 258) By omitting the
context about Smith, and the first three words of Marx’s sentence, Clarke
portrays Marx as commenting on the actualities of capital rather than on his
predecessor’s mistake. [2] The Moscow edition reads “thing at rest” (Marx, 1957: 105); the German “ruhendes Ding” is closer to “dormant thing”, suggesting that capital is alive but asleep, (Marx, 1966b: 109) [3] Marx calls capital “self-valorising value”, a
formula helpful only to those who
already know what he means, putting it better as “value which maintains
itself”, and still better as “value which produces surplus-value.” (Marx, 1978:
185; 1971: 131, and 475) Even that third rendition requires knowing what he
means by value. Talk of capital as self-expanding value sounds like Mr Toad’s
puffing himself up. Marx ridicules writers who regard capital “as a mere number
that increases itself, just as Malthus saw people in his geometrical
progression.” (Marx, 1981: 520) To portray capital as self-expanding implies
that its drivers are immanent instead of the outcome of conflicting practices,
not all of them internal. [4] Because this essay draws on the less frequently consulted Theories of Surplus-Value readers are reminded of Oakley (1985). [5] Not everyone is convinced that Marx could extricate
himself from his initial “wrong” formulation by claiming that “our manner of
speaking does no harm; it serves, rather, as an abbreviation.” (Marx, 1976:
152) Disputes over value-forms are associated with I.I. Rubin in 1928, the Japanese
school around Uno Kozo from the
1950s and the defence of
intrinsic-value by Andrew Kliman against neo-Ricardian allegations of its
redundancy. [6] Compare this stance with his pre-Marxist training
“that human behaviour cannot be measured.” (Harvey, 1969: vi) A reluctance to
count is not shared by Leibniz, for whom “[r]elative things have their quantity
as well as absolutes; for instance, ratios or proportions in mathematics have
their quantity, and are measured by logarithms, and yet they are relations.
Thus although time and space consist in relations, they have their quantity
none the less.” (Leibniz, 1934: 225) Michael
A. Lebowitz ends his appreciate review of The
Limits to Capital by pointing out that “the absence of mathematical proofs
is a serious flaw,” Monthly Review,
June 1986, p. 41. |
See also: Valorisation |