CAPITAL - Accounting for Capital |
Accounting for Capital The contributions of Rob A. Bryer My work with Marx explores whether
accounting can help us understand and test the quintessence of his thought, particularly
the central principle that the origin of all surplus is unpaid labour. Rob. A. Bryer, ‘Marx and accounting’
(1999)[1]
My
first uncertainty has been what to call this paper – ‘Accounting for capital’
or ‘No accounting for capital’. What follows moves in and out of the approaches
implied by those alternatives, with ‘accounting’ both a matter of measuring the
return on investment and of holding capital to account for the havoc it
unleashes through its need to expand. The implications of ‘capital’ are so multiplex
that every effort to define it is caught in conceptual disputes within
bourgeois economics, among Marxists and between schools of accounting,
intricacies integral to introducing the work of Rob A. Bryer. A straw poll among my contacts has not
come up with anyone who had heard of him, apart from two Sydney academics who had
rented him a room at Royal Leamington
Spa in the late 1970s. So the unicorn of a Marxist Professor of Accounting does
exist. I regret not knowing about his work when preparing The Essence of Capitalism in the late 1990s, or when trying to make
sense of the continuing blockage in the expansion of capital. I stumbled upon
him late last year in a footnote to an article on accounting practices in early
nineteenth-century Britain[2]
as I began sorting out when and how value became self-valorising. No author has
been more stimulating. None has presented more challenges. A further uncertainty is how to
introduce Bryer’s engagement with the materialist conception of history. How
would you outline the four volumes of Marx’s Capital to an audience who knew next to nothing about that work?
Bryer is not Marx yet the task is no less forbidding. A summary of nearly a
million words is not so much difficult as pointless. Indeed, I might just as
well read out the titles of his twenty-seven articles. Hence, I have decided to
encourage a wider readership by dropping a payload of incendiaries to disturb,
in the manner of Marx, Nietzsche or Freud, and in keeping with Bryer’s
combative style. I shall do so by taking three of his most contentious positions:
the first on how to define capital/ism; the second on what he calls the ‘spurious’
transformation problem; and the third on when did the U.S. of A. became
capitalist. The three topics intersect around his emphasis on social capital. Look! No maths! While
editing volume two of Capital, Engels
grumbled about Marx’s shaky grasp on commercial arithmetic: The preparation of this chapter [XV]
for publication presented no small number of difficulties. Firmly grounded as
Marx was in algebra, he did not get the knack of handling figures, particularly
commercial arithmetic. Although there exists a thick batch of copybooks
containing numerous examples of all kinds of commercial computations which he
had solved himself. But knowledge of the various methods of calculation and
exercise in daily practical commercial arithmetic are by no means the same, and
consequently Marx got so tangled up in his computations of turnovers that
beside places left uncompleted, a number of things were incorrect and
contradictory.[3] As
the manager of the English branch of his family business, Engels had absorbed
the ‘daily practical’ experience required to correct Marx’s howlers. This once,
I feel that my level of understanding is closer to Marx’s than to that of
Engels. Before going further into Bryer’s life
and works, I should warn you that my knowledge of accounting did not get off to
a good start. On leaving school in 1959, I joined the accounts branch of the
then Commonwealth Department of Social Services. I enrolled for Accounting I at
the university where the lecturer spent three hours on Wednesday nights with
his back towards the class as he wrote on the blackboard. No quantify of
No-Doze could keep any of us awake. I quit after the first term, retreating
into Public Administration I. As soon as I earned any income from my pen I knew
I had to hire a tax accountant. These days I add up the income and expenses for
the quarterly GST statements but rely on an accountant to submit the annual
income tax returns. I know what deprecation means but do not trust myself with
a spreadsheet. This aversion to ‘sums’ weakens my investigation of capital
expansion. In addition, I am not equipped to evaluate the ‘accounting’ parts of
Bryer’s articles. In preparing The Essence of Capitalism in the late 1990s, I did venture into the
disputes over how to report intangibles, notably brands and goodwill. Bertell
Ollman joked about his being an innumerate on the editorial board of Critical Perspectives on Accounting,
which had started in 1989 as a Marxist scholarly journal, with several
Australian advisors. Had I not been so tunnel-visioned in pursuit of
malpractice, I might have noticed Bryer’s early articles there. I did see some
non-Marxist academic heavyweights contributing to debates about ‘value’, uneasy
at the subjective nature of their own definitions. I took away enough to see
the implosion of the dot.com boom coming. The Bulletin had rejected my article but then rang up wanting it after
the bubble burst.[4] I knew how to tell a
ledger from leger-de-main. The little more I now know about the language
and concepts of accounting I have absorbed from studying Bryer. Hence, there is
no point in asking me to evaluate his defence of British practice as objective
against the subjectivity of U.S. Financial Accounting Standards Board (FASB). My prejudices are all on his side but
they are worth less than a share in Jodee Rich’s One.Tel. Bryer has convinced me that a critique of
political economy can be neither materialist nor historical unless it engages
with accounting practices. Accounting generates little enthusiasm
on the far Left, where it is seen as training servants of capital, ever more so
since the arrival of fee-paying Schools of Business. Marxists need to lift our
gaze from the flies around the honey pot of corruption[5]
to see that the expansion of capital is shaped not just by fraud but through
acceptable accounting practices. Bryer shows that ENRON followed the subjective
assumptions of the FASB (2004b). Marxists have neglected the weight that Marx
gives to swindling in the tussles between capitalists to carve up surplus value
while it is being realised as profit.[6]
An average rate of profit is never an absolute but, like the law of its falling
rate, operates tendentially, with accounting malpractice among the
counter-tendencies. I have been bashing on for forty years
about the need for the Left to get into ‘capital history’ to balance ‘labour
history’ as a step towards writing history as class struggle. Nonetheless, my
essay about ‘Capital’ around the year 1913 in the National Museum catalogue for
the Canberra centenary exhibition gave no thought to accounting until it was
too late to acknowledge how inadequate book-keeping and auditing practices
remained twenty years after the crash of 1893. The best I could do after
reading Bryer was to add a segment to an on-line version. I hope that that insertion
means that I am not too old to learn. At one level, a list of Bryer’s
articles should be enough to send historical materialists scurrying after the
pieces directly related to their research topics. Having studied his 1,800 pages, I recommend total
immersion. An example drawn from the 2012 Historical Materialism conference illustrates
the benefits that flow from using accounting to write history, an altogether
different enterprise from chasing up the stories of accounting practices. Last year, Dick Bryan and Mike
Rafferty proposed that the past thirty years of financialisation had added to
the risks facing investors. Bryer’s interrogation of accounting practices
across three centuries, and not only in the United States, makes their claim
hard to accept. The nature and sources of risk have altered, but there has
rarely been so much as a single decade within even one nation-market-state
where investors could be confident about the numbers they were getting from the
managers or auditors of their money-capital. Bryan and Rafferty pay almost no
attention in their 2006 book to the way investors might evaluate risk through accounts
and audits, citing only one accounting article, and that about cotton mills
around 1900.[7] Bryer is not alone in
documenting the effort that the directors and/or managers had put into
concealing as much as they did know from shareholders, for example, the Royal
Mail case from the late 1920s revealed that the empire’s most distinguished
auditor had signed off on the use of reserves to pay dividends. More common was
the practice at Coats and Co. in restricting dividends to retain reserves for
expansion, or to weather downturns.[8]
Transparency improved after the U.K. Securities Exchange Acts of 1933 and 1934
and more so with the UK Companies Act of 1948.
Britain’s High Court remains reluctant to second guess decisions by
boards of directors. Curriculum
vitae Bryer
does not promote himself as an historian of accounting. He is, of course,
across the technical and conceptual matters pursued by scholars who delight in
showing that few practitioners of double-entry bookkeeping bothered to
calculate profit, or even to draw out annual balances from the debit and credit
entries.[9]
Rather, he pictures himself as an accounting historian, that is, an historical
materialist who investigates accounting practices in order to write the history
of capital. He uses the ways that businesses have kept their books to determine
when the expansion of capital came to dominate economic life. Specifically, he
looks for when capitalist farmers began chasing a return on investment (ROI) and
not just a surplus. Although Bryer’s incursions into the metamorphoses of modes
of production are what interest me most, I shall not here dig into their rich
lode for the revolution in capital afater 1800. One reason why Bryer’s contributions
are not better known is that he has not produced a book around their themes. Although
a selection of essays would be welcome, the best solution would be for four volumes,
one each on the accounting history of British economy since feudalism; a second
on the US of A; a third one on Marx(-ism) and accounting; and a fourth exposing
the subjective nature of the accounting standards promoted by the U.S. profession. Appendix II has
grouped Bryer’s articles under these four heads. Since the essays need editing
to remove repeats of information and reasoning, Bryer perhaps feels that it is
more important to push into new fields, as he has done since 2012 on U.S. capitalism,
rather than to reshape what he had made available. The benefits from his four
pieces on the U.S. of A. more than outweigh any loss from a reluctance to take
the time to integrate his pieces on Britain. Before embarking on a survey of
capital through accounting, Bryer had contributed to the struggle against
Thatcherism by analysing the books of the steel industry and Britain’s
state-owned enterprises. (see his chapters in Fighting Closures, 1984) He remains an activist by intervening in
disputes over accounting standards. Warwick Inc. A
working-class lad from Exeter, Bryer graduated in 1977 from the University of Warwick
where, since 1991, he has taught accounting in its school of business. That institution
resonates in this, the golden jubilee year of The Making of the English Working Class by Warwick’s foundation
professor of history, E.P. Thompson, who oversaw the publication of a philippic,
Warwick University Ltd, in 1970, to storm out in protest against the
university’s takeover by business.[10] In a quirk of fate, Warwick Business
School has become the base for a critic of capitalism, rigorous and
substantial, at once historically informed and penetratingly conceptual. Had
Thompson been around for a further twenty years there is an outside chance that
he might have learned some Marxism from Bryer. However, Thompson’s ‘perturbed spirit’ is likely to be as
hostile to a Marxist accountant as it was to the Business School or to Marx’s method,
smacking, as it must, of theory and economic laws. Historical materialists have much more
to learn about exploitation from Bryer than from Thompson who was innocent of
political economy, if not actively hostile to its prominence.[11]
The gulf between them is obvious from the latter’s most cited article, ‘Time,
Work-Discipline, and Industrial Capitalism’ (1967),[12]
which includes nary a word on labour-time as the measure of value, or on
turnover times, or production periods. He pictures time’s being spent rather
than labour-time’s being purchased, alongside the cliché about time being money
instead of units of labour-time finding their universal equivalent in money. Thompson
does not reject the labour theory of value but proceeds as if it never existed,
as indicated by his giving no footnote to any of Marx’s writings, unlike Brian
Harrison a few pages on in the same issue for his essay on ‘Religion and
Recreation in Nineteenth-century England’. Thompson would not have had to delete
more than a couple of turns of phrase from The
Making of the English Working Class had Marx never written Capital. Thompson’s
maxim that class is a relationship not a thing has been a soporific to
generations of students seeking the lazy option of writing about the past
without an inkling of political economy. For the working class, class
consciousness is the experience of responding to being treated as a thing, as a
factor of production, that is, variable capital. That Thompson’s repulsion at
the laws of capital expansion has not turned off many labour historians tells us something about the triumph of
bourgeois hegemony over that redoubt in academe. Bryer is orthodox on the labour theory
of value (1994a), the transformation problem and valorisation, even though he
arrives at those positions by novel routes. As an historical materialist, he
puts class struggle front and center, in line with Rodney Hilton, Robert
Brenner and Ellen Meiskins Wood, breaking from G. Cohen to support Wood on
whether the social relations of production are the economic base. He thereby
recognises why ‘accounting is an essential element of the political
organisation of surplus extraction.’[13]
In addition, he stresses the differences between the formal and the real
subordination (‘subsumption’) of labour to capital. How to relate that pair to
absolute and relative surplus value and then all four to simple and expanded production
is one of the more daunting tasks when pursuing the revolution in capital. By contrast, the post-Foucauldian
Richard H. Macve confuses the exploitation of labour with the creation of
capital. Although Marx shows that capital is the product of its own reproduction,
he does not imagine that capital is the immediate result. For Bryer, ‘Marx’s sojourn in production is
based on this “double result” by chapter 5, that “Capital cannot therefore
arise from circulation, and it is equally impossible for it arise apart from
circulation”.’[14] Labour does not directly
produce capital, or even profit, but, rather supplies the surplus value from
which the agents of capital must still secure their profits and, only after
that battle, are able to reinvest to accumulate more capital. This circuitry
reminds us that the class struggle within capitalism is never confined to the
points of production of surplus value. Unlike the generality of academic Marxists,
Bryer has never sought to make a name for himself by colonising a crack in Marx’s
edifice to announce how cleverer he is than its architect. On the contrary, Bryer
has devoted himself - ‘virtually alone, but undaunted’, as he puts it - to
demonstrating how capitalism and accounting are ‘consistent’ with Marx’s
critique of political economy, a quod
erat demonstrandum which alienates neo-classicals and post-Foucauldians
alike, as it will neo-Ricardians. Despite Bryer’s being ever ready to accept that
‘we need further research’, one colleague learnt first hand that ‘Rob feels
most at home with passionate, in-your-face discourse, no quarter asked or
given.’[15]
Bryer is unmoved: ‘Though it would be nice to agree about something,’ is as
much as he will concede, pointing out that, because ‘the theories contradict
each other on fundamental issues, compromise does not seem tenable’. His style
of presentation matches his refusal to extract the best from all possible stews,
instead taking his stand with Marx who never concealed his contempt for
Ricardo’s epigones who had voided their master’s voice: The last form is the academic form, which proceeds
historically and, with wise moderation, collects the ‘best’ from all courses,
and, in doing this, contradictions do not matter; on the contrary, what matters
is comprehensiveness. All systems are thus made insipid, their edge is taken
off and they are gathered together peacefully in a miscellany. The heat of
apologetics is moderated here by erudition, which looks down benignly on the
exaggerations of economic thinkers, and merely allows them to float as oddities
in its mediocre pap. Since such works appear only when political economy has
reached the end of its scope as a science, they are at the same time the graveyard of this science.[16]
The
sterility of disputes over the value to be added by dividing pin-heads is perhaps
behind Frank Stillwell’s pleas for a pluralist fusion under the banner of heterodox
political economy – not its Critique?. The obverse danger threatens when he recommends
the higher journalism of J.K. Galbraith’s The
Great Crash to understand the current crisis in the expansion of capital.[17] We
can now introduce Bryer’s three provocations: 1. capital/ism defined; 2. the
transformation non-problem; and 3. the re-dating of U.S. capitalism. 1. Defining capital/ism Keenest
for a conference of historical materialists is Bryer’s attention to ‘social
capital’. On the need to refine the Marxist treatment of capital I am with him
all the way as I labour to specify how and when capital became the product of
its own reproduction. ‘Why?’ it did so is a question we dare not ask for fear
of being snared by the Great Satan of teleology. Bryer’s investigations of the zig-zags
towards capitalism kept me going through his hundreds of pages. At last, here
was an author who took the defining of capital as pivotal to Marxism. As befits
an historical materialist, Bryer has learnt by doing, deepening his grasp of how
capital expands by finding fresh facets to dissect before integrating the
results with a refashioning of the concepts that he had deployed to reach the
new level of relative knowledge. No one does a better job than Bryer at
refining the definition of capitalism whereas the attempts by most Marxists are
almost as gestural as those from bourgeois ideologues who either make one
element represent the whole, or toss wage-labour, credit, factories and
steam-engines into the pot after the manner of the witches in Macbeth, Act 4, sc I: Surge in
trade, divided skill, Navvy’s
spade, exchange of bill, Engine’s
steam, and low piece-rate Goldsmith’s
loan and factory gate For
a mode of powerful trouble. Like
a hell-broth boil and bubble. No
shopping list of causes can explain a putative industrial revolution, let alone
the revolution in capital. Bryer’s accounting history provides a means to
redeem the concept of capital-within-capitalism from the thicket of quasi- and
pseudo-definitions whose proponents seldom stop to define ‘capital’. Beyond
asserting that it is a relationship and a process but not a thing,[18]
Marxists are as guilty here as anybody, indeed, more so, since we are supposed
to know best on this topic, if no other. Were we anywhere other than at a
conference of historical materialists, I should have to risk insulting my
audience by explaining that, for Marxists, ‘historical’ is not a narrative -
neither grand, nor petit - about the
past, anymore than materialism is the celebration of greed or a reduction of ‘sensuous
human activity’ to organic matter. To say that Marxism is an historical science
is to say that nothing human is universal, eternal or natural,[19]
a rule which applies to concepts[20]
as much as to the actualities in which they deal: ‘For each mode’, Bryer notes,
‘there is a different mode of accounting and mode of accountability.’[21]
In 1994, he analysed three broad phases of demesne farming in order to track
developments in manorial accounting,[22]
and has since provided tools for
identifying the shift between each stage in the movement towards social capital
and then within its engrossment and geographic spread. Whether the historical applies to
every crevice of the natural world need not derail us here since it is sufficient
to be confident that viewing human history as an unbroken arc provides, as Marx
quipped, a ‘very impressive method – for swaggering, sham-scientific, bombastic
ignorance and intellectual laziness. ‘[23]
Materialists, therefore, periodise more exactly than into three, five or six
modes - give or take the Asiatic. In regard to capitalism, Marx talks of
‘Period One’ with its ‘sediment’ from previous modes and ‘Period Two’ when
capital has become the ‘product of its own reproduction’.[24]
Lenin set out ‘three principal stages in the history of monopolies’ within the
forty years up to 1903 by when, ‘capitalism has been transformed into imperialism.’[25] If this level of understanding of the
import of periodisation for a materialist conception of history is a
commonplace among Marxists, it is not so widely understood why Marx’s social
capital is on an altogether different plane, both in actuality and in thought,
from Eva Cox’s mantra. For a start, social capital is far from sociable. Bryer
contributes to periodisation by showing why social capital is unique to the
capitalist mode, a defining characteristic, necessary but not sufficient for
capital to become the product of its own reproduction. Relentless expansion
proved possible once joint-stock companies with limited liability allowed more
individual capitals to be socialised. Social capital matches social labour just
as free capital does free labour. At a terminological level, capital moves from
the plurals of individual capitals and socialised ones to the singular of
social capital, which is a unity of competing capitals, some individual but
mostly socialised. Bryer is adamant that ‘total social’ is not the mere adding
up of individual and socialised capitals – not an aggregation - but rather the
outcome of one of those qualitative leaps so treasured by us dialecticians. Social
capital is capital-within-capitalism, the result of the revolution in capital. Bryer establishes a test for what is
and what is not capitalist, in short, for recognising the triumph of a new
mode. A basis for refutation is available according to whether a farmer or firm
is calculating a Return on Investment. Accounting history points to a way for
Marxists to deflect Karl Popper’s accusation that Marxism can never be a
science because it offers no means for refuting its propositions. The practice of accounting history also supplies
the criterion that allows us to decide when the pursuit of ROI has become
generalised through expanded reproduction. Too few account books survive from
before 1800 to let us decide how many proprietors passed Bryer’s test. Popper’s
requirement for a science is not that its practitioners demolish their own
premises, merely that their methods include some means for so doing.[26]
Bryer’s test is clear-cut for whether
particular farmers were agrarian capitalists: is the farmer content to gain a
surplus or is he trying to improve the return on investment (ROI)?[27]
That principle applies to every owner or
controller of productive property - whether banker, manufacturer or merchant -
who must reinvest most of their earnings if they are to continue as capitalists
against competitors, an imperative intensified in the era of oligopoly. Most investors
remain caught in what Marx calls ‘a Faustian conflict between the passion for
accumulation and the desire for enjoyment’, so that they do not always live by
‘Moses and the Prophets: Accumulate! Accumulate!’,[28]
but dabble in both splendour and speculation. That their risk-taking in the
days before limited liability might have cost them their fortunes,[29]
in no sense dilutes Bryer’s acid test for determining whether they had been
performing as the personifications of capital, as suggested by Flieschman in
the three-way debate. (2005a) 2. Transformation transfigured At
our initial gathering in 2011, Mike Beggs invited us to stop worrying about the
transformation problem.[30]
From the floor, Rick Kuhn reacted with one of the standard defences. Three
years before, Bryer had stood the problem on its feet to argue that there is no
problem.[31] No one who reads his
sixty pages will be able to stop worrying or to regurgitate either the old-time
hymns or the ‘tautological’ New Interpretation.[32]
For Bryer, the ‘transformation problem’ is one of several ‘spurious problems’
created by economists, including
Marxist ones. In the Abstract to his ‘Marx’s accounting solution to the
“transformation problem” ’, Bryer contends that, far from Marx’s having failed
to transform values into prices, he ‘theorised capitalist accounting to solve
the reverse of the economists’ problem’, so that his triumph is to reveal ‘how
capitalists transform the general rate of profit and prices of production into socially
necessary labour time.’ On encountering this
transmogrification of transformation, I had to have a cup of tea, a Bex and a nice
lie down. Somewhat restored, I read how economists refuse to see that Marx’s
solution to the transformation problem is, first, historical, secondly, reliant
on capitalist accounting, and, thirdly, presupposes the ‘really difficult’ history
of ‘total social capital’, capitalists functioning as a living collective,
demanding the general rate of profit, and competing individual capitalists
using accounts to control their labour processes to transform prices of
production into socially necessary labour times, which they account for at what
accountants today call standard or target costs. (2008: 4) If the capitalist treats profit as
surplus value ‘the price of production = cost price + profit = k + p = k + s;
i.e. in practice it is equal to the value of the commodity’. (Marx, Capital, v. 3, Penguin, p. 309) Marx did not need to perform a
mathematical transformation to know that under total social capital and
competition, capitalists would value constant and variable capital at the cost
price necessary to equalize the required return on capital. In short, … capitalists would
transform the general rate of profit and price of production into the money
value of socially necessary labour in production. (2008: 40) Despite
Bryer’s disparagement of ‘mathematical transformation’, he supplies five pages
of hieroglyphs. My low level of maths means that assessing that usual method of
grappling with the ‘transformation problem’ is beyond me. The most I can manage
is to evaluate the coherence of the versions being presented, which, in Bryer’s
case, sets out a line of reasoning which Marxists cannot ignore. One ground for a positive response is
that I remain persuaded by the labour theory of value as the keystone to a
critique of capital expansion. A second, and exogenous appeal is Bryer’s historical
materialist approach in standing Marx back on his feet for, as Marx reminds us,
‘mysteries which mislead theory into mysticism find their rational solution in
human practice and the comprehension of this practice.’[33]
Or, as he later wrote in one of a series of letters to Engels about accounting:
The method of businessmen is, of
course, partly based on illusions and even greater than those of the
economists; on the other hand it [accounting] rectifies the latter’s
theoretical illusions by means of practical ones.[34] Nothing
is more practical to capitalists than winning the class struggle for the hourly
extraction of surplus value from the units of labour-time they purchase; that
fact is the substance of the Manifesto’s
claim that ‘[t]he written history of all hitherto existing society is the
history of class struggles’.[35]
Sad to say, no matter how much we enjoy having our prejudices confirmed, they
do not an argument win. 3. Not born on the Fourth of July Elizabeth
Humphrys’ paper at the 2012 conference accepted that settler Australia had been
born capitalist.[36] But what if Britain had
not been capitalist in 1787 when the First Fleet set sail? That is one more challenge
from Bryer’s investigations. His approach encourages my current effort to
identify the revolution in capital as a counter to the bourgeois propaganda for
an industrial revolution which – it now seems - never quite happens, and against
the technological determinists for whom nothing else much matters.[37] Instead of delving into what has been
awry with the ‘transition’ debate, I trust that I can excite interest in Bryer’s
‘accounting history’ by summarising his most recent work which focuses on north
America from early settlement to the Enron collapse. The conclusion, which will
make many of you bristle, is that the United States did not become capitalist
until the first twenty years of the twentieth century. Yes, you heard right –
between 1900 and 1920. To reach this position, Bryer relies on evidence from a
minority of US progressive scholars such as Michael Merrill,[38]
and on the business history establishment around Alfred Du Pont Chandler,
although he shunts aside Chandler’s claims for the transformative impact of
railroad managers. Bryer contributes no primary research into the actualities
of these business practices or class struggles, just as I lack the depth of
scholarship to evaluate his use of secondary sources. No Grand Canyon opens in
the line of argument. I have yet to absorb all the
implications of Bryer’s argument about capital’s not becoming fully operational
in the U.S. of A. for some sixty years after it had become so in the United
Kingdom. Nothing he reports conflicts with what I had picked up while working
on the corporate form taken by social capital around 1900 for The Essence of
Capitalism. The difficulty I have is not with his conclusion about the US
of A. My panic is how to integrate that birthdate for U.S. capitalism with the
current consensus that ‘the industrial revolution’ did not become fully
operational in England until the dawn of monopolising capitals around 1870.[39]
In short, is there a bridge between the
two, and, if so, on which concepts is it built? More clues to a its
construciton, I suspect, are in Bukharin’s Imperialism
than in Lenin’s Imperialism but more
still in his The Development of
Capitalism In Russia. Apart from the revisions that Bryer distils
from secondary materials, his originality is in dissecting a clutch of US
economic and accounting authors in the decades before the Great Depression,
integrating evidence about changes in the economy with shifts in bourgeois ideology
and practices, and all viewed through the prism of Marx’s critique. The result
is as sound a model for a materialist history of ideas as Dobb’s 1937 Political Economy and Capitalism. Pivotal
to Byrer’s investigation is how class struggles around the moment of the U.S. breakthrough into
fully operational capitalism contributed to economic nostrums which continue to
grease the redirection of accounting principles and practices. Bryer contends
that a 1906 work by Irving Fischer laid a foundation for the rewriting of
accounting rules as subjective. Across 600 printed pages, Bryer surveys
accounting ideas and performance to explicate his opposition to the recent
pressure on the rest of the world to adopt U.S. accounting precepts. (2013c and
d) Marxian slips Before
you rush off to engage with Bryer, a few minor caveats are advisable regarding his
manner of presentation. Sometimes, his choice of words slowed my taking the
most from his insights. These phrases range from the mundane to the conceptual.
When he writes ‘According to Marx’s theory’ he usually means no more than ‘from
a Marxist perspective’, and often says as much by way of elegant variation.
Indeed, ‘theory’ regularly means hypothesis. Unlike Thompson, he is not averse
to theory. More worrying are terms which carry
ideological burdens. Highest among these possible sources of confusion is Bryer’s
stress on ‘mentality’ as a measure of whether an individual, group or mode is
capitalist. Even more than does Max Weber,[40]
Bryer is not one to mistake a ‘mentality’ for a disembodied idea but recognises
a set of social practices around record-keeping for the purpose of securing a
Return on Investment. He offers a cute metaphor about account books being the
superstructure stretched over a base of exploitation. The second concerns is that in recent
years, Bryer has displaced ‘social
capital’ with Marx’s penchant for ‘total social’. If total is not aggregate,
why affix either qualifier? The differentiations are between individual,
socialised and social. If ‘total’ is not meant to convey aggregate, but refers
to the dissolution of barriers to the flows of money-capital through as wide as
possible a market, then to write about ‘total social’ is at best redundant and
at worst misleading. Bryer has given up referring to ‘semi-capitalist’ and
‘capitalistic’ for the early elements
of the individual and the socialised capitals. As uneasy as I am with ‘total
social’, my real annoyance is that I cannot come up with a term that are more
apposite to the revolution in capital and easier to use when explaining that
upheaval. His earlier trio of individual/socialised/social limited the
likelihood of misunderstanding ‘social’ as no more than a larger version of
socialised. A further troubling but widespread slip
is to activate the categories as Bryer does in upending the transformation
problem: History created the general rate of
profit and total social capital, which now requires individual capitalists to
make the transformation from market prices to values rather than, as usually
understood, to make the transition from values to prices. (2008:. 4) His
subsequent sentences make it clear that he means that the transformation
problem had been solved in practice across a couple of hundred years of class
struggle - not by the Platonic form of History with a capital-H descending from
the heavens: The history of the general rate of
profit is the history of the socialisation of capitals – beginning in England
in the late 16th century, growing from the late 17th
century, but flowering from the middle of the 19th century, and
spectacularly as total social capital from its end. [i.e. by 1900] The history of social capital is the
‘really difficult’ interconnected histories of merchants, farmers, landlords,
peasants, workers, industrialists, joint-stock companies, capital markets and
accounting. (p. 23) This
mixing of social classes with the institutions that their numbers create
illuminates the materialist concept of history, ‘consistent with Marx’s theory’
that ‘history’ does nothing, since it can be made only by real living people.[41] Bryer’s troubling expressions are
outweighed many times over by the richness of his concepts and data. Whenever I
squirmed at a choice of words I found, as I read on, that he had strayed into neither
Idealism nor mechanistic materialism. Trial balance As
outrageous Bryer’s conclusions can seem at first, they are always anchored in
evidence and arrived at through a critique of political economy. The re-dating
of the triumph of capitalism in the U.S. of A. to the early twentieth century is
but the most recent shocker. Even if we end up rejecting one or other of Bryer’s
conclusions, the challenges posed by his data and methods will make us more
competent as historical materialists. In my case, his writings clear a path
towards what I have taken to calling the revolution in capital after 1800 in
opposition to the technocratic and other bourgeois notions of an industrial
revolution years earlier. In the three-way contest against Richard Fleischman
for Adam Smith and Richard H. Macve for the post-Foucauldians over the
significance of cost accounting at the Carron Company in the late eighteenth
century,[42] Bryer proved that there
is no sharper sparring partner. (2005a) APPENDIX
I: Works by Rob A. Bryer (1991) ‘Accounting for the “Railway Mania”
of 1845 – A Great Railway Swindle?’, Accounting,
Organisaitons and Society, 16 (5/6), 1991, pp. 439-86. (1993a) ‘The Late Nineteenth Century
Revolution in Financial Reporting: Accounting for the Rise of Investor or
Managerial Capitalism’, Accounting, Organizations And Society, 18,
1993, pp. 649-690. (1993b) ‘Double-entry Book-keeping and the
Birth of Capitalism: Accounting for the Commercial Revolution in Northern
Italy’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 4 (1993), pp. 113-140. (1994a) ‘Why Marx’s Labour Theory is
Superior to the Marginalist Theory of Value: The Case from Modern Financial
Reporting’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 5, 1994, pp. 313-340.
(1994b) ‘Accounting for the Social
Relations of Feudalism’, Accounting and Business Research, 24, (1994),
pp. 209-228. (1995) "A Political Economy of SSAP22:
Accounting for Goodwill". British Accounting Review, 27, 1995,
pp. 283-310. (1997) ‘The Mercantile Laws Commission of
1854 and the Political Economy of General Limited Liability’, Economic
History Review 50, 1997, pp. 36-54. (1998a) "The Struggle to Maturity in
Writing the History of Accounting, and the Promise’, Critical Perspectives
on Accounting, 9, 1998, pp. 669-681. (1998b) ‘The Laws of Accounting in Late
Nineteenth Century Britain’, Accounting History, 31, 1998, pp. 1-40. (1999a) ‘A Marxist Critique of the FASBs
Conceptual Framework’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 10, 1999,
pp. 551-589. (1999b) ‘Marx and Accounting’, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, 10, 1999, pp. 683-709. (2000a) ‘The history of accounting and the
transition to capitalism. Part one: theory’, Accounting, Organizations And
Society 25, 2000, pp. 131-161. (2000b) ‘The history of accounting and the
transition to capitalism. Part two: evidence’, Accounting, Organizations
And Society 25, 2000, pp. 327-381. 2004a) ‘ “Mirror, Mirror, on the wall,
which is the fairest value of all?” Fair values in global accounting – ideal
way or wrong track?’, 2004 Lecture, Bayreuth. (2004b) ‘Accounting lessons from Enron:
fraud, aggressive accounting or the wrong cnceptual framework’, draft 2004. (2004c) ‘The Roots of Modern Capitalism: A
Marxist Accounting Hsitory of the Origins and Consequences of Capitalist
Landlords in England’, Accounting
Historians Journal, 31 (1), June 2004, pp. 1-56. (2005a) ‘Smith, Marx or Foucault in
understanding the early Industrial Revolution” A re-examination of management
and accounting for capital and labour at the Carron Company’, Presented at
Goteborg, May 2005. (2005b) ‘A Marxist accounting history of
the British Industrial Revolution: a review of evidence and suggestions for
research" Accounting, Organizations And Society 30 (2005, pp.
25-65. (2006a) ‘A Political Economy of Accounting
and control of the labour process’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting
,17, 2006, pp. 551-598. (2006b), ‘Capitalist accountability and the
British Industrial Revolution: The Carron Company, 1759-circa. 1850’, Accounting,
Organizations And Society, 31, 2006, pp. 687-734. (2006c), ‘The genesis of the capitalist
farmer: towards a Marxist accounting history of the origins of the English
agricultural revolution’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting 17
(2006, pp. 367-397. (2008) ‘Marx’s acounting solution to the
‘transofrmatin problem’, Draft 2008. (2011) ‘A review of John Richard Edwards
and Stephen P. Walker, (Eds) The Routledge Companion to Accounting History (
London and New York: Routledge, 2009)’, British Accounting Review ,43,
2011, pp. 324-325. (2013a) ‘Part 1: Was America Born
Capitalist?’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 23, 2012, pp. (2013b) ‘Part 2: The rise of the ‘modern
business enterprise’, America’s transition to capitalism, and the genesis of
management accounting’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 24, 2013,
pp. ??. (2013c) ‘Part 3: Adam Smith, the rise and
fall of socialism, and Irving Fisher’s theory of accounting’, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, 24, 2013, pp. ??? (2013d) ‘Part 4: ‘Creating the ‘big mess”:
the influence of Irving Fischer’s neoclassical theory of acoucnting on the
stock market crash of 1929’, draft ·
‘Part 4: ‘Creating the ‘big mess”: the
influence of Irving Fischer’s neoclassical theory of acoucnting on the stock
market crash of 1929’, draft ·
‘Part 3: Adam Smith, the rise and fall of
socialism, and Irving Fisher’s theory of accounting’, Critical Perspectives
on Accounting, 24, 2013, pp. ??? ·
‘Part 2: The rise of the ‘modern business
enterprise’, America’s transition to capitalism, and the genesis of management
accounting’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 24, 2013, pp. ??. ·
‘Part 1: Was America Born Capitalist?’, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, 23, 2012, pp.
Accounting standards
·
‘A Marxist Critique of the FASBs Conceptual
Framework’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 10, 1999, pp.
551-589. ·
‘The
Struggle to Maturity in Writing the History of Accounting, and the Promise’, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, 9, 1998, pp. 669-681. ·
‘A
Political Economy of SSAP22: Accounting for Goodwill’, British Accounting
Review, 27, 1995, pp. 283-310. ·
‘Marx’s acounting solution to the
‘transformation problem’, Draft 2008. ·
‘Smith, Marx or Foucault in understanding the
early Industrial Revolution: A re-examination of management and accounting for
capital and labour at the Carron Company’, Presented at Goteborg, May 2005. ·
‘A Political Economy of Accounting and control
of the labour process’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting ,17, 2006,
pp. 551-598. ·
‘Marx and Accounting’, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, 10, 1999, pp. 683-709. ·
‘Why Marx’s Labour Theory is Superior to the
Marginalist Theory of Value: The Case from Modern Financial Reporting’, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, 5, 1994, pp. 313-340. Accounting and British capitalism ·
‘The Laws of Accounting in Late Nineteenth
Century Britain’, Accounting History, 31, 1998, pp. 1-40. ‘The
Late Nineteenth Century Revolution in Financial Reporting: Accounting for the
Rise of Investor or Managerial Capitalism’, Accounting, Organizations and
Society, 18, 1993, pp. 649-690. ·
‘A Marxist accounting history of the British
Industrial Revolution: a review of evidence and suggestions for research" Accounting,
Organizations and Society 30 (2005, pp. 25-65. ·
‘The history of accounting and the transition
to capitalism. Part one: theory’, Accounting, Organizations and Society
25, 2000, pp. 131-161. ·
‘The history of accounting and the transition
to capitalism. Part two: evidence’, Accounting, Organizations and Society
25, 2000, pp. 327-381. ·
‘Accounting for the “Railway Mania” of 1845 –
A Great Railway Swindle?’, Accounting,
Organisaitons and Society, 16 (5/6), 1991, pp. 439-86. ·
‘The Mercantile Laws Commission of 1854 and
the Political Economy of General Limited Liability’, Economic History
Review, 50, 1997, pp. 36-54. ·
‘Capitalist accountability and the British
Industrial Revolution: The Carron Company, 1759-circa. 1850’, Accounting,
Organizations and Society, 31, 2006, pp. 687-734. ·
‘The Roots of Modern Capitalism: A Marxist
Accounting Hsitory of the Origins and Consequences of Capitalist Landlords in
England’, Accounting Historians Journal,
31 (1), June 2004, pp. 1-56. ·
‘The genesis of the capitalist farmer: towards
a Marxist accounting history of the origins of the English agricultural revolution’,
Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 17, 2006, pp. 367-397. ·
‘Accounting for the Social Relations of
Feudalism’, Accounting and Business Research, 24, (1994), pp.
209-228. ‘Double-entry Book-keeping and the Birth of
Capitalism: Accounting for the Commercial Revolution in Northern Italy’, Critical
Perspectives on Accounting, 4 (1993), pp. 113-140. [1] Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 10,
1999, p. 683. [2] A.J.
Arnold and S. McCartney, ‘ “Veritable gold mines before the arrival of railway
competition”: but did dividends signal rates of return in the English canal
industry?’, Economic History Review (EcHR), 64 (1), 2011, p. 235. [3] F.
Engels in Karl Marx, Capital, v. II,
Penguin, London, 1978, pp. 359-60. Engels later observed: ‘Marx, too, had made
similar [mathematical] mistakes, and was right for all that about many things’,
‘Preface’, Marx, Capital, v. III,
Penguin, London, 1981, p. 109. The editors of the Penguin translation found a
mistake in calculating percentages which Engels had missed, p. 560n. Marx also
made an error about rents in that volume, Penguin, p. 839n. [4] see
my The Essence of Capitalism,
Sceptre, Sydney, 2001, pp. 64-70. [5]
Abraham J. Briloff, ‘Unaccountable Accounting Revisited’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 4 (4), December 1993, pp.
301-33. [6] Karl
Marx, Capital, v. I, Penguin, London,
1976, p. 907n.; v. II, 1978, pp. 97, 137 and 584-5; v. III, 1981, pp. 321,
569-73 and 741-2; Theories of
Surplus-Value (TS-V), v. III,
Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1971, p. 454. Engels observed how ‘the American
prepares himself by a series of bankruptcies, genuine and fraudulent, for the
role of millionaire,’ Marx-Engels
Selected Works, v. III, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1970, p. 383. Marx warns how attention to
‘cheating’ in the circulation process deflects attention from exploitation in
the production process, Capital, v.
III, p. 966. [7] Dick
Bryan and Michael Rafferty, Capitalism
with derivatives: a political economy of financial derivatives, capital and
class, Palgrave, London, 2006; J. Toms, ‘Cotton Mills 1870-1914’, Accounting, Organisation and Society,
27, 2002, pp. 61-84. [8] Kirsten W. Kininmonth, ‘Stitching it up:
accounting and financial control at J & P Coats Ltd, c. 1890-1960’, Accounting History, 12 (4), 2007, pp.
367-91. [9] For
instance, Basil Yamey, ‘Some Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century Double-Entry
Ledgers’, Accounting Review, 34 (4),
October 1959, pp. 534-46; Sybil M. Jack, ‘An Historical Defence of Single Entry
Book-keeping’, Abacus, 2 (2),
December 1966, pp. 137-58. [10] But
see Zenon Bankowski and Geoff Mungham, ‘Warwick
University Ltd (Continued)’, British
Journal of Law and Society, 1 (2), Winter 1974, pp. 179-184. [11] In
light of Thompson’s disposition, and his attachment to William Morris, the
neglect of the wealth of nature in his output is no less a puzzle than his
spurning of political economy. The resonance of Thompson’s title with W.G.
Hoskins’s The Making of the English
Landscape (1955) echoes in its prose style: What else has
happened in the immemorial landscape of the English countryside? Airfields have
flayed it bare wherever there are level, well-drained stretches of land, above
all in eastern England. Poor devastated Lincolnshire and Suffolk! And those
long gentle lines of the dip-slope of the Cotswolds, those misty uplands of the
deep-grey oolite, how they have lent themselves to the villainous requirements
of the new age! Over them drones, day after day, the obscene shape of the
atom-bomber, laying a trail like a filthy slug upon Constable’s and
Gainsborough’s sky. England of the Nissen hut, the ‘pre-fab’, and the electric
fence, around some unmentionable devilment … England of the bombing-range
wherever there was once silence, as on Otmoor or the marshlands of
Lincolnshire; England of battle-training areas on the Breckland heaths, and
tanks crashing through empty ruined Wiltshire villages; England of high
explosive falling upon the prehistoric monuments of Dartmoor. Barbaric England
of the scientists, the military men, and the politicians: let us turn away and
contemplate the past before all is lost to the vandals. pp. 253-4. [12] E.P.
Thompson, Past & Present, 38,
December 1967, pp. 56-97. [13] Rob
A. Bryer, ‘Marx
and Accounting’, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 10, 1999, p.
689. [14]
Marx, Capital, v. I, 1976, p. 268. [15] A
description which Thompson’s admirers and detractors have applied to him, Roger
Wells, ‘E.P. Thompson, customs in common and moral economy’, Journal of Peasant Studies, 21 (2), 1993,
pp. 298-301. [16]
Marx, TS-V, v. III, p. 502. [17] Australian Options, Winter 2013, p. 20;
Summer 2008/09, p. 6. [18] See my ‘The “massiness” of capital’, Journal of Australian Political Economy,
70, Summer 2012/13, pp. 25-46. [19] Marx, Capital,
v. III, pp. 752, 963-4, 969-70 and 1018;
TS-V, III, p. 259. [20] F.
Engels, ‘Preface’, Marx, Capital, v.
III, p. 103; Engels to Schmidt, 12 March 1895, Marx-Engels Selected Correspondence, Foreign Languages Publishing
House, Moscow, n.d., pp. 562-3. [21]
Bryer, ‘Marx and Accounting’, 1999, p. 686. [22] R.A.
Bryer, ‘Accounting for the Social Relations of Feudalism’, Accounting and Business Research, 24 (95), 1994, pp. 218ff. [23] Karl Marx to Ludwig Kugelmann, 27 June 1870, M-ECW, v. 43, Lawrence & Wishart,
London, 1988, p. 527; cf. Karl Marx, Grundrisse,
Penguin, London, 1973, p. 85. [24]
Marx, TS-V, III, pp. 491-2. [25] V.I. Lenin, Imperialism, The Highest
Stage of Capitalism, A Popular Outline, Foreign Languages Press, Peking,
1975, p. 20. [26] Karl
R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations,
The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1972
ed., pp. 33-65. [27] The
Marxist Stefano Fenoaltea in ‘Authority, Efficiency,
and Agricultural Organization in Medieval England and Beyond: A Hypothesis’, Journal of Economic History, 35 (4),
December 1975, pp. 693-718, is confident that landlords knew the value
of their fixed capital, but never once does he mention book-keeping let alone
the levels of numeracy, Keith
Thomas, ‘Numeracy in Early Modern England’, Royal
Historical Society Transactions, Fifth Series, volume 37, 1987, pp.
103-132, where the footnotes are a bibliography to numeracy in other times and
places. The record-keeping at monasteries was exceptional, J. A. Raftis, ‘Western Monasticism and Economic
Organization’, Comparative Studies in
Society and History, 3 (4), July 1961, pp. 452-469. [28]
Marx, Capital, v. 1, pp. 741-2. [29] R.H.
Campbell, ‘The Law and the Joint-Stock Company in Scotland’, Peter L. Payne
(ed.), Studies in Scottish Business
History, Frank Cass, London, 1967, pp. 136-51. [30] Mike
Beggs, ‘Zombie Marx and Modern Economics, or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and
Forgot the Transformation Problem’, Journal
of Australian Political Economy, 70, Summer 2012/13, pp. 11-24. [31] But
not the line of William J. Baumol, ‘The Transformation of Values: What Marx
“Really” Meant (An Interpretation)’, Journal
of Economic Literature, 12 (1), March 1974, pp. 51-62. [32]
Neither Andrew Kliman nor Bryer mentions the other. [33] Marx-Engels Collected Works (M-ECW), v. 5, Lawrence & Wishart,
London, 1976, pp. 5 and 8. [34] Marx
to Engels, 5 March 1858, M-ECW, v.
40, Lawrence & Wishart, London, 1983, p. 283. [35] M-ECW, v. 6, Lawrence & Wishart,
London, 1976, pp. 482 – as corrected by Engels in 1888. [36]
Elizabeth Humphrys, ‘The Birth of Australia: Non-Capitalist Social Relations in
a Capitalist Mode of Production?’, Journal
of Australian Political Economy, 70, Summer 2012/13, pp. 110-29. [37] G.A.
Cohen, ‘Restricted and Inclusive Historical Materialism’, Edna Ullmann-Margalit
(ed.), ‘The Prism of Science’, Boston
Studies in the Philosophy of Science, v. 95, 1986, pp. 57-83. [38]
Michael Merrill, ‘Putting “capitalism” in its place: A Review of Recent
Literature’, William & Mary Quarterly,
Third Series, 52 (2), April 1995, pp. 315-26. [39] Raphael Samuel, ‘The Workshop of the
World: Steam Power and Hand Technology in Mid-Victorian Britain’, History Workshop, 3, Spring 1977, pp.
6-72. [40]
Appreciation of Weber’s materialist treatment of calculation in the origins of
capitalism is not helped by the failure of both translators of The Protestant Ethic and the’ Spirit’ of
Capitalism to retain the inverted commas that he placed around ‘Geist’ (‘Spirit). [41] M-ECW, v. 4, Lawrence & Wishart,
London, 1975, p. 93. [42] Cf. R.H.
Campbell, ‘The Financing of Carron Company’, Business History, 1. (1), December 1958, pp. 21-34; Rob A.
Bryer, ‘Capitalist
accountability and the British Industrial Revolution: The Carron Company,
1759-circa. 1850’, Accounting, Organizations and Society, 31, 2006,
pp. 687-734. |
See also: Marxism |